Logic Terms and Definitions
Logic Basics
Bound Variable
Definition:
A variable that is within the scope of a quantifier (∀,∃) or binding operator, where its value is controlled by that operator. Denoted like: ∀x(P(x)) or ∃x(Q(x)), where x is bound
- Cannot be freely substituted
- Value determined by quantifier
- Same variable can be bound differently in different scopes
Bound variables in:
∀x(x > 0): x is bound by ∀
∃y(y² = 2): y is bound by ∃
∫₀¹ x dx: x is bound by integral
Nested scopes:
∀x∃y(x < y): both x and y are bound
∀x(x > 0): x is bound by ∀
∃y(y² = 2): y is bound by ∃
∫₀¹ x dx: x is bound by integral
Nested scopes:
∀x∃y(x < y): both x and y are bound
Unbound Variable
Definition:
A variable that appears in a formula without being controlled by any quantifier or binding operator. Also called a free variable. In P(x,y), both x and y are unbound if no quantifiers are present
- Can be freely substituted
- Value not controlled by formula
- Must be specified externally
Free variables:
P(x): x is free
x + y = 5: both x and y are free
Mixed example:
∀x(P(x,y)): x is bound, y is free
P(x): x is free
x + y = 5: both x and y are free
Mixed example:
∀x(P(x,y)): x is bound, y is free
Proposition
Definition:
A declarative statement that is either true or false, but not both. Also called a propositional variable or atomic formula in formal logic.
- Must be declarative (not a question or command)
- Must be unambiguous
- Truth value is independent of observer
Valid propositions:
- "2 + 2 = 4"
- "Paris is the capital of France"
- "All integers greater than 2 are prime"
Not propositions:
- "x + 1 = 5" (variable statement)
- "How old are you?" (question)
- "Go to sleep" (command)
- "2 + 2 = 4"
- "Paris is the capital of France"
- "All integers greater than 2 are prime"
Not propositions:
- "x + 1 = 5" (variable statement)
- "How old are you?" (question)
- "Go to sleep" (command)
Predicate
Definition:
A statement containing variables that becomes a proposition (true/false) when those variables are given specific values. Denoted as P(x), Q(x,y), etc., where P, Q are predicates and x, y are variables in their domains.
- Returns a truth value when variables are specified
- Forms basis for quantified statements
- Domain must be specified for each variable
Single variable predicate:
P(x): "x is prime"
- P(2) is true
- P(4) is false
Two variable predicate:
Q(x,y): "x is greater than y"
- Q(5,3) is true
- Q(2,7) is false
P(x): "x is prime"
- P(2) is true
- P(4) is false
Two variable predicate:
Q(x,y): "x is greater than y"
- Q(5,3) is true
- Q(2,7) is false
Fundamental for expressing mathematical statements and forming basis for predicate logic and quantifiers
Quantifier
Definition:
A logical operator that specifies the quantity of specimens in a domain for which a predicate holds. Two main types: universal quantifier (∀: 'for all') and existential quantifier (∃: 'there exists')
- Has scope of application
- Can be nested
- Can be negated
Universal quantifier:
∀x(x2≥0) - "For all x, x squared is non-negative"
Existential quantifier:
∃x(x2=2) - "There exists x where x squared equals 2"
Combined quantifiers:
∀x∃y(y>x) - "For all x there exists y greater than x"
∀x(x2≥0) - "For all x, x squared is non-negative"
Existential quantifier:
∃x(x2=2) - "There exists x where x squared equals 2"
Combined quantifiers:
∀x∃y(y>x) - "For all x there exists y greater than x"
Negating quantifiers:
- ¬(∀x)P(x)≡∃x(¬P(x))
- ¬(∃x)P(x)≡∀x(¬P(x))
- ¬(∀x)P(x)≡∃x(¬P(x))
- ¬(∃x)P(x)≡∀x(¬P(x))
Elementary Proposition
Definition:
An atomic statement P that has a truth value and cannot be decomposed into simpler logical statements
- Atomic (indivisible)
- Truth-valued
- Independent
- Basic building block
- Binary truth value
- No internal logical structure
- Can be negated
- Combines with connectives
Basic Statements:
"It is raining"
"2 is prime"
"The sky is blue"
Counter-examples (not elementary):
"It is raining and cold" (compound)
"If x>0 then x²>0" (conditional)
"All numbers are positive" (quantified)
- Foundation for complex logic
- Truth table construction
- Propositional calculus
- Logical analysis
- Cannot express quantification
- No internal structure
- No predicates
- No variables
Partial Proposition
Definition:
An incomplete logical statement φ(x₁,...,xₙ) containing free variables or undefined terms that requires additional context to determine truth value
- Contains free variables
- Truth value undefined
- Context dependent
- Requires completion
- Open formulas
- Templates
- Schemata
- Placeholders
Predicate Logic:
P(x): "x is prime"
Q(x,y): "x is greater than y"
Templates:
"If ___, then ___"
"___ is a ___ of ___"
- Variable binding
- Substitution
- Context provision
- Quantification
Complete Proposition
Definition:
A logical statement p that is fully specified and has a well-defined truth value under any given interpretation I
- Has definite truth value
- No free variables
- Context independent
- Well-formed formula
- Ground formulas
- Closed formulas
- Sentences
- Full assertions
Atomic Propositions:
"2 is prime"
"Today is Monday"
"Water freezes at 0°C"
Compound Propositions:
"If it rains, then the ground is wet"
"All natural numbers are either even or odd"
"(2 + 2 = 4) ∧ (3 × 3 = 9)"
- Truth value determinable
- Interpretation independent
- Testable conditions
- Logical evaluation
Reasoning
Inference
Definition:
A logical process of deriving a conclusion from given premises through valid logical rules. Symbolically: If P₁, P₂, ..., Pₙ are premises and C is conclusion, write: P₁, P₂, ..., Pₙ ⊢ C
- Must follow valid rules of logic
- Preserves truth from premises to conclusion
- Can be direct or indirect
- Forms basis of mathematical proofs
Modus Ponens:
P₁: p → q
P₂: p
∴ q
Modus Tollens:
P₁: p → q
P₂: ¬q
∴ ¬p
P₁: p → q
P₂: p
∴ q
Modus Tollens:
P₁: p → q
P₂: ¬q
∴ ¬p
- Direct inference
- Conditional inference
- Deductive reasoning
- Inductive reasoning
- Transitive inference
Proof
Definition:
A logical argument that demonstrates the truth of a statement (conclusion) from given or previously established statements (premises, axioms) through valid rules of inference. Written as: Given P₁,...,Pₙ, prove C
- Each step must be justified
- No circular reasoning allowed
- Assumptions must be stated clearly
- Must be complete and rigorous
- Proof by contradiction
- Proof by contrapositive
- Mathematical induction
- Proof by cases
- Existence proofs
- Uniqueness proofs
Standard format:
1. Given/Assumptions
2. Statement to prove
3. Logical steps
4. Therefore conclusion
1. Given/Assumptions
2. Statement to prove
3. Logical steps
4. Therefore conclusion
Direct proof example:
Prove: If n is even, then n² is even
Proof:
- Let n be even
- Then n = 2k for some integer k
- n² = (2k)² = 4k² = 2(2k²)
- Therefore n² is even
Prove: If n is even, then n² is even
Proof:
- Let n be even
- Then n = 2k for some integer k
- n² = (2k)² = 4k² = 2(2k²)
- Therefore n² is even
Premise
Definition:
A proposition or statement (P₁, P₂, ..., Pₙ) assumed or proven to be true, from which a conclusion is drawn. In formal logic notation, premises are listed above a horizontal line with conclusion below: CP1,P2,...,Pn
- Truth value must be known or assumed
- Can be axioms, definitions, or proven statements
- Independent of conclusion being proven
Syllogism premises:
P₁: All men are mortal
P₂: Socrates is a man
C: Therefore, Socrates is mortal
Logical form:
P₁: p → q
P₂: p
C: Therefore, q
P₁: All men are mortal
P₂: Socrates is a man
C: Therefore, Socrates is mortal
Logical form:
P₁: p → q
P₂: p
C: Therefore, q
- Minor premise (specific instance)
- Hidden/Implicit premises
- Axioms (taken as self-evident)
Conclusion
Definition:
The statement C derived from premises P₁, P₂, ..., Pₙ through valid logical inference. In formal notation: P₁, P₂, ..., Pₙ ⊢ C or CP1,P2,...,Pn
- Truth value depends on:
• Truth of premises
• Validity of inference rules
- Cannot contain new variables not in premises
- Strength depends on premise support
Valid conclusion:
P₁: If it rains, ground is wet
P₂: It is raining
C: Therefore, ground is wet
Formal logic:
P₁: p → q
P₂: p
C: ∴ q
P₁: If it rains, ground is wet
P₂: It is raining
C: Therefore, ground is wet
Formal logic:
P₁: p → q
P₂: p
C: ∴ q
A conclusion is valid if:
- Premises are true
- Rules of inference are correct
- No logical fallacies present
- Premises are true
- Rules of inference are correct
- No logical fallacies present
Validity
Definition:
An argument is valid if and only if it is impossible for all premises to be true and the conclusion false. In formal notation: if premises P₁, P₂, ..., Pₙ are true, then conclusion C must be true: (P₁ ∧ P₂ ∧ ... ∧ Pₙ) → C
- Depends only on logical structure
- Preserved through valid inference rules
- Different from soundness (valid + true premises)
Valid but not sound:
P₁: All cats are green
P₂: Whiskers is a cat
C: Therefore, Whiskers is green
(Valid structure, false premise)
Valid and sound:
P₁: All squares have 4 sides
P₂: Figure A is a square
C: Therefore, Figure A has 4 sides
P₁: All cats are green
P₂: Whiskers is a cat
C: Therefore, Whiskers is green
(Valid structure, false premise)
Valid and sound:
P₁: All squares have 4 sides
P₂: Figure A is a square
C: Therefore, Figure A has 4 sides
Ways to test validity:
- Truth tables
- Formal proofs
- Counter-example method
- Venn diagrams
- Truth tables
- Formal proofs
- Counter-example method
- Venn diagrams
Soundness
Definition:
The property of an argument being both valid and having true premises.
Argument
Definition:
A logical structure consisting of premises P₁, P₂, ..., Pₙ and a conclusion C where the premises are meant to support the conclusion. In formal notation: P₁, P₂, ..., Pₙ ⊢ C or CP1,P2,...,Pn
- Must have exactly one conclusion
- Can be valid or invalid
- Can be sound or unsound
- Form determines validity, not content
Deductive argument:
P₁: All mammals are warm-blooded
P₂: All dogs are mammals
C: Therefore, all dogs are warm-blooded
Symbolic form:
P₁: p → q
P₂: r → p
C: Therefore, r → q
P₁: All mammals are warm-blooded
P₂: All dogs are mammals
C: Therefore, all dogs are warm-blooded
Symbolic form:
P₁: p → q
P₂: r → p
C: Therefore, r → q
- Inductive (conclusion probable but not certain)
- Direct (straight line of reasoning)
- Indirect (proof by contradiction)
Deduction
Definition:
A form of logical inference where a conclusion necessarily follows from a set of premises. If all premises are true, the conclusion must be true.
- Moves from general to specific
- Truth-preserving when valid
- Conclusion certainty depends on premises
- Forms basis of mathematical proofs
- Modus Ponens: ((P → Q) ∧ P) ⊢ Q
- Modus Tollens: ((P → Q) ∧ ¬Q) ⊢ ¬P
- Hypothetical Syllogism: ((P → Q) ∧ (Q → R)) ⊢ (P → R)
Mathematical:
Premise 1: All integers divisible by 4 are even
Premise 2: 12 is divisible by 4
Conclusion: Therefore, 12 is even
Real-world:
Premise 1: All mammals are warm-blooded
Premise 2: Dogs are mammals
Conclusion: Therefore, dogs are warm-blooded
- Mathematical proofs
- Legal reasoning
- Computer programming
- Scientific hypothesis testing
Induction
Definition:
A method of reasoning that derives general principles from specific observations, establishing probable (not certain) conclusions.
- Moves from specific to general
- Conclusion extends beyond premises
- Results in probability, not certainty
- Subject to new evidence
- Simple Enumeration: observing pattern in instances
- Elimination: removing alternative explanations
- Analogy: reasoning from similar cases
- Statistical Inference: generalizing from samples
Mathematical:
Observation 1: 1 = 1
Observation 2: 1 + 2 = 3
Observation 3: 1 + 2 + 3 = 6
Conjecture: Sum of first n integers = n(n+1)/2
Scientific:
Observation: Every observed swan is white
Induction: Therefore, all swans are white
(Note: Shows limitation - black swans exist)
- Problem of induction (Hume)
- Cannot guarantee universal truth
- Susceptible to counterexamples
- Requires representative samples
Logical Consequence
Definition:
A statement φ is a logical consequence of premises Γ (written Γ ⊨ φ) if φ is true in every model where all premises in Γ are true
- Transitive: If A⊨B and B⊨C, then A⊨C
- Monotonic in classical logic
- Independent of syntax
- Preserved under substitution
- Semantic consequence (model-theoretic)
- Syntactic consequence (proof-theoretic)
- Material consequence
- Strict consequence
Semantic Consequence:
Premises:
- All humans are mortal
- Socrates is human
Consequence:
- Socrates is mortal
Material Consequence:
Premises:
- If it rains, streets are wet
- Streets are not wet
Consequence:
- It is not raining
- A ⊨ B iff A → B is valid
- Γ ⊨ φ iff Γ ⊢ φ (completeness)
- Truth preservation
- Necessity preservation
Substitution
Definition:
An operation σ that replaces variables or subexpressions with other expressions. Formally: σ: V → Terms where V is the set of variables
- Preserves well-formedness
- Compositional
- Type-preserving
- Capture-avoiding
- Variable substitution
- Term substitution
- Expression substitution
- Pattern substitution
Variable Substitution:
P(x) [x/a] = P(a)
Term Substitution:
(x + y)[x/(a+b)] = (a+b) + y
Formula Substitution:
(P → Q)[P/R∧S] = ((R∧S) → Q)
- Proof steps
- Equation solving
- Unification
- Pattern matching
Foundations
Axiom
Definition:
A statement accepted as true without proof in a logical system.
Theorem
Definition:
A statement that has been proven based on axioms and logical rules.
Errors In Logic
Fallacy
Definition:
A flaw or error in reasoning that renders an argument invalid.
Truth Values
Contradiction
Definition:
A statement that is always false regardless of the truth values of its components.
Tautology
Definition:
A compound proposition that evaluates to true for all possible truth values of its variables. In formal notation: if T is tautology, then T ≡ 1 or ⊨ T
- Truth table shows all true results
- Used in proving logical equivalence
- Negation is a contradiction
Common tautologies:
- Law of excluded middle: p ∨ ¬p
- Double negation: p 𠪪p
- Modus ponens: ((p → q) ∧ p) → q
Truth table for p ∨ ¬p:
p | ¬p | p ∨ ¬p
T | F | T
F | T | T
- Law of excluded middle: p ∨ ¬p
- Double negation: p 𠪪p
- Modus ponens: ((p → q) ∧ p) → q
Truth table for p ∨ ¬p:
p | ¬p | p ∨ ¬p
T | F | T
F | T | T
Can be verified by:
- Truth tables
- Logical equivalences
- Formal proofs
- Truth tables
- Logical equivalences
- Formal proofs
Truth Table
Definition:
A systematic listing of all possible combinations of truth values for atomic propositions and the resulting truth values of compound expressions
- Input columns (atomic propositions)
- Intermediate columns (subexpressions)
- Output column (final result)
- 2ⁿ rows for n variables
- Validity checking
- Satisfiability testing
- Logical equivalence
- Circuit design
Simple AND (P ∧ Q):
P | Q | P ∧ Q
T | T | T
T | F | F
F | T | F
F | F | F
Implication (P → Q):
P | Q | P → Q
T | T | T
T | F | F
F | T | T
F | F | T
- Tautology detection
- Contradiction detection
- Equivalence checking
- Minimal forms
Inference Rules
Modus Ponens
Definition:
A fundamental rule of inference: given (P → Q) and P, we can deduce Q. Formally written as: QP→Q,P or (P → Q) ∧ P ⊢ Q
- Valid for any propositions P and Q
- Forms basis for direct proofs
- Cannot be applied in reverse
Logical form:
P₁: P → Q (If P then Q)
P₂: P (P is true)
C: Therefore, Q (Q must be true)
Real example:
P₁: If it rains, then streets are wet
P₂: It is raining
C: Therefore, streets are wet
P₁: P → Q (If P then Q)
P₂: P (P is true)
C: Therefore, Q (Q must be true)
Real example:
P₁: If it rains, then streets are wet
P₂: It is raining
C: Therefore, streets are wet
Used in:
- Mathematical proofs
- Programming logic
- Legal reasoning
- Everyday inference
- Mathematical proofs
- Programming logic
- Legal reasoning
- Everyday inference
Modus Tollens
Definition:
A rule of inference: given (P → Q) and ¬Q, we can deduce ¬P. Formally written as: ¬PP→Q,¬Q or (P → Q) ∧ ¬Q ⊢ ¬P
- Valid for any propositions P and Q
- Contrapositive of Modus Ponens
- Often used in proof by contradiction
Logical form:
P₁: P → Q (If P then Q)
P₂: ¬Q (Q is false)
C: Therefore, ¬P (P must be false)
Real example:
P₁: If it's raining, ground is wet
P₂: Ground is not wet
C: Therefore, it's not raining
P₁: P → Q (If P then Q)
P₂: ¬Q (Q is false)
C: Therefore, ¬P (P must be false)
Real example:
P₁: If it's raining, ground is wet
P₂: Ground is not wet
C: Therefore, it's not raining
Used in:
- Indirect proofs
- Scientific reasoning (falsification)
- Diagnostic reasoning
- Error detection
- Indirect proofs
- Scientific reasoning (falsification)
- Diagnostic reasoning
- Error detection
Disjunctive Syllogism
Definition:
A rule of inference: given (P ∨ Q) and ¬P, we can deduce Q. Formally written as: QP∨Q,¬P or (P ∨ Q) ∧ ¬P ⊢ Q
- Valid for any propositions P and Q
- Works with either disjunct being false
- Requires exclusive OR not necessary
Logical form:
P₁: P ∨ Q (Either P or Q)
P₂: ¬P (Not P)
C: Therefore, Q (Q must be true)
Real example:
P₁: Either it's day or night
P₂: It's not day
C: Therefore, it's night
P₁: P ∨ Q (Either P or Q)
P₂: ¬P (Not P)
C: Therefore, Q (Q must be true)
Real example:
P₁: Either it's day or night
P₂: It's not day
C: Therefore, it's night
Used in:
- Process of elimination
- Troubleshooting
- Decision making
- Case analysis
- Process of elimination
- Troubleshooting
- Decision making
- Case analysis
Rule Of Inference
Definition:
A pattern of reasoning Γ ⊢ φ that preserves truth, where Γ is a set of premises and φ is the conclusion
- Modus Ponens: P→Q, P ⊢ Q
- Modus Tollens: P→Q, ¬Q ⊢ ¬P
- Hypothetical Syllogism: P→Q, Q→R ⊢ P→R
- Disjunctive Syllogism: P∨Q, ¬P ⊢ Q
- Resolution: (P∨Q), (¬P∨R) ⊢ Q∨R
- And-Introduction: P, Q ⊢ P∧Q
- Or-Introduction: P ⊢ P∨Q
- Universal Instantiation: ∀xP(x) ⊢ P(a)
Modus Ponens Example:
1. If it rains, the ground is wet (P→Q)
2. It is raining (P)
Therefore: The ground is wet (Q)
Resolution Example:
1. Either John or Mary is guilty (P∨Q)
2. John is not guilty (¬P)
Therefore: Mary is guilty (Q)
- Truth-preserving
- Validity guaranteed
- Independent of content
- Formal correctness
Logical Connectives
Conjunction
Definition:
A logical operation combining two statements P and Q with AND (∧), true only when both statements are true. Formally: P ∧ Q is true iff both P and Q are true
- Associative: (P ∧ Q) ∧ R ≡ P ∧ (Q ∧ R)
- Idempotent: P ∧ P ≡ P
- Identity: P ∧ true ≡ P
Truth table:
P | Q | P ∧ Q
T | T | T
T | F | F
F | T | F
F | F | F
Real example:
P: It's raining
Q: It's cold
P ∧ Q: It's raining and cold
P | Q | P ∧ Q
T | T | T
T | F | F
F | T | F
F | F | F
Real example:
P: It's raining
Q: It's cold
P ∧ Q: It's raining and cold
De Morgan's Law: ¬(P ∧ Q) ≡ ¬P ∨ ¬Q
Disjunction
Definition:
A logical operation combining two statements P and Q with OR (∨), true when at least one statement is true. Formally: P ∨ Q is true iff either P is true or Q is true (or both)
- Associative: (P ∨ Q) ∨ R ≡ P ∨ (Q ∨ R)
- Idempotent: P ∨ P ≡ P
- Identity: P ∨ false ≡ P
Truth table:
P | Q | P ∨ Q
T | T | T
T | F | T
F | T | T
F | F | F
Real example:
P: It's sunny
Q: It's cloudy
P ∨ Q: It's either sunny or cloudy
P | Q | P ∨ Q
T | T | T
T | F | T
F | T | T
F | F | F
Real example:
P: It's sunny
Q: It's cloudy
P ∨ Q: It's either sunny or cloudy
De Morgan's Law: ¬(P ∨ Q) ≡ ¬P ∧ ¬Q
Conditional
Definition:
A logical operation denoted as P → Q (if P, then Q), establishing a relationship where P implies Q. Formally written as: if P is true and P → Q is true, then Q must be true
- Not commutative: P → Q ≢ Q → P
- Transitive: If P → Q and Q → R, then P → R
- Contrapositive equivalence: P → Q ≡ ¬Q → ¬P
- False antecedent: If P is false, P → Q is true (vacuously true)
- Negation: ¬(P → Q) ≡ P ∧ ¬Q
Mathematical:
P: n is even
Q: n² is even
P → Q: If n is even, then n² is even
Real-world:
P: It rains
Q: The ground is wet
P → Q: If it rains, then the ground is wet
P: n is even
Q: n² is even
P → Q: If n is even, then n² is even
Real-world:
P: It rains
Q: The ground is wet
P → Q: If it rains, then the ground is wet
Antecedent
Definition:
In a conditional statement P → Q, the antecedent P is the hypothesis or condition that implies the consequent
- Acts as the "if" part of an "if-then" statement
- Determines the domain or conditions under which the implication holds
- Can be simple (P) or compound (P ∧ R)
- Strength of antecedent affects the logical strength of the conditional
- Multiple antecedents can be combined: (P ∧ Q) → R
Mathematical:
In "If x > 0, then x² > 0"
Antecedent is "x > 0"
Real-world:
In "If it rains, then the ground is wet"
Antecedent is "it rains"
In "If x > 0, then x² > 0"
Antecedent is "x > 0"
Real-world:
In "If it rains, then the ground is wet"
Antecedent is "it rains"
Consequent
Definition:
In a conditional statement P → Q, the consequent Q is the conclusion or result that follows from the antecedent
- Acts as the "then" part of an "if-then" statement
- Need not be causally related to antecedent
- Can be simple (Q) or compound (Q ∨ R)
- Multiple consequents possible through conjunction
- Forms basis for modus ponens inference rule
Mathematical:
In "If x > 0, then x² > 0"
Consequent is "x² > 0"
Real-world:
In "If it rains, then the ground is wet"
Consequent is "the ground is wet"
In "If x > 0, then x² > 0"
Consequent is "x² > 0"
Real-world:
In "If it rains, then the ground is wet"
Consequent is "the ground is wet"
Biconditional
Definition:
A logical operation denoted as P ↔ Q (P if and only if Q), indicating that P and Q have the same truth value. Formally: (P → Q) ∧ (Q → P)
- Commutative: P ↔ Q ≡ Q ↔ P
- Transitive: If P ↔ Q and Q ↔ R, then P ↔ R
- Equivalence relation: defines logical equivalence
- Stronger than simple conditional: requires both directions
- P ↔ Q ≡ (P → Q) ∧ (Q → P)
- P ↔ Q ≡ (P ∧ Q) ∨ (¬P ∧ ¬Q)
- ¬(P ↔ Q) ≡ P ⊕ Q (exclusive or)
Mathematical:
P: x² = 4
Q: x = ±2
P ↔ Q: x² = 4 if and only if x = ±2
Real-world:
P: Today is a weekend
Q: Today is Saturday or Sunday
P ↔ Q: Today is a weekend if and only if it's Saturday or Sunday
Logical Connective
Definition:
Operators that combine simple propositions into compound propositions, forming the basic building blocks of logical expressions
- Unary connectives: negation (¬)
- Binary connectives: conjunction (∧), disjunction (∨)
- Implications: conditional (→), biconditional (↔)
- Other: exclusive or (⊕), NAND (↑), NOR (↓)
- Truth-functionality: output determined by inputs
- Completeness: some sets of connectives are functionally complete
- Interdefinability: connectives can define each other
- Precedence: standard order of operations
Basic Combinations:
P ∧ Q: Conjunction (AND)
P ∨ Q: Disjunction (OR)
¬P: Negation (NOT)
P → Q: Implication (IF-THEN)
P ↔ Q: Biconditional (IF AND ONLY IF)
- {¬, ∧} is functionally complete
- {¬, ∨} is functionally complete
- {↑} (NAND) is functionally complete alone
- {↓} (NOR) is functionally complete alone
- Digital circuit design
- Programming language operators
- Database queries
- Artificial intelligence logic
Implication
Definition:
A logical relationship P → Q between statements P (antecedent) and Q (consequent) where P implies Q. The implication is false only when P is true and Q is false.
- Not commutative: P → Q ≢ Q → P
- Not associative: (P → Q) → R ≢ P → (Q → R)
- Equivalent to ¬P ∨ Q
- Vacuously true when P is false
- Material implication: truth-functional P → Q
- Strict implication: necessarily P → Q
- Counterfactual: if P were true, Q would be true
- Causal implication: P causes Q
Mathematical:
P: n is prime
Q: n has exactly two factors
P → Q: If n is prime, then n has exactly two factors
Real-world:
P: It is raining
Q: The ground is wet
P → Q: If it is raining, then the ground is wet
- Modus Ponens: ((P → Q) ∧ P) ⊢ Q
- Modus Tollens: ((P → Q) ∧ ¬Q) ⊢ ¬P
- Hypothetical Syllogism: ((P → Q) ∧ (Q → R)) ⊢ (P → R)
P | Q | P → Q
T | T | T
T | F | F
F | T | T
F | F | T
- Affirming the consequent: ((P → Q) ∧ Q) ⊬ P
- Denying the antecedent: ((P → Q) ∧ ¬P) ⊬ ¬Q
- Mistaking correlation for causation
Equivalence
Definition:
Two logical statements p and q are equivalent (p≡q) if they have identical truth values under all possible valuations of their variables
- p≡p
- Symmetric: if p≡q then q≡p
- Transitive: if p≡q and q≡r then p≡r
Common equivalences:
p→q≡¬p∨q
(p∧q)≡¬(¬p∨¬q) (De Morgan's Law)
¬¬p≡p (Double Negation)
p→q≡¬p∨q
(p∧q)≡¬(¬p∨¬q) (De Morgan's Law)
¬¬p≡p (Double Negation)
Can be proven using truth tables or logical proofs
Negation
Definition:
A unary logical operator (¬P or ~P) that reverses the truth value of a proposition P. If P is true, ¬P is false; if P is false, ¬P is true.
- Involution: ¬(¬P) ≡ P (double negation law)
- Contradictions: P ∧ ¬P is always false
- Tautologies: P ∨ ¬P is always true
- Basic completeness: {¬, ∧} or {¬, ∨} are functionally complete
- De Morgan's Laws:
¬(P ∧ Q) ≡ ¬P ∨ ¬Q
¬(P ∨ Q) ≡ ¬P ∧ ¬Q
- Implication: ¬(P → Q) ≡ P ∧ ¬Q
- Biconditional: ¬(P ↔ Q) ≡ P ⊕ Q
Mathematical:
P: x > 0
¬P: x ≤ 0
Logical:
P: All ravens are black
¬P: Some ravens are not black
Real-world:
P: It is raining
¬P: It is not raining
- Proof by contradiction
- Boolean algebra
- Digital circuit design
- Database queries
Compound Proposition
Definition:
A proposition p constructed by combining simpler propositions using logical connectives. Formally: p := q ∘ r where ∘ ∈ {∧, ∨, →, ↔}
- Simple propositions
- Logical connectives
- Grouping symbols
- Precedence rules
- Binary connective usage
- Unary negation
- Proper parenthesization
- Well-formed combinations
Basic Forms:
P ∧ Q (conjunction)
P ∨ Q (disjunction)
P → Q (implication)
Complex Forms:
(P ∧ Q) → R
¬(P ∨ Q) ∧ (R → S)
(P → Q) ↔ (¬Q → ¬P)
- Truth-functional
- Component-based
- Precedence-respecting
- Context-independent
Logic
Disjunctive Normal Form (DNF)
Definition:
A logical formula is in DNF if it is a disjunction (OR) of conjunctions (AND) of literals (variables or their negations): (p∧q)∨(¬p∧r)∨(q∧r)
- Every formula can be converted to DNF
- Each conjunction is a minterm
- No conjunction contains both a variable and its negation
- No distributive laws needed after conversion
Converting to DNF:
Complex example:
(p→q)≡(¬p∨q)
(p↔q)≡(p∧q)∨(¬p∧¬q)
Complex example:
¬(p∧q)≡(¬p∨¬q)
Conjunctive Normal Form (CNF)
Definition:
A logical formula is in CNF if it is a conjunction (AND) of disjunctions (OR) of literals (variables or their negations): (p∨q)∧(¬p∨r)∧(q∨r)
- Every formula can be converted to CNF
- Each disjunction is a maxterm
- No disjunction contains both a variable and its negation
- Useful in automated theorem proving
Converting to CNF:
Complex example:
(p→q)≡(¬p∨q)
(p↔q)≡(p∨¬q)∧(¬p∨q)
Complex example:
¬(p∨q)≡(¬p∧¬q)
Quantifiers
Universal Quantifier
Definition:
Denoted by ∀x P(x), asserts that predicate P holds for every element x in the domain of discourse. Read as 'for all x, P(x)'
- Distributes over conjunction: ∀x(P(x) ∧ Q(x)) ≡ ∀xP(x) ∧ ∀xQ(x)
- Does not distribute over disjunction: ∀x(P(x) ∨ Q(x)) ≢ ∀xP(x) ∨ ∀xQ(x)
- Ordering matters with different quantifiers
- Empty domain: ∀xP(x) is vacuously true
- ¬(∀xP(x)) ≡ ∃x¬P(x)
- Double negation: ¬(¬(∀xP(x))) ≡ ∀xP(x)
- Important in proofs by contradiction
Mathematical:
∀x(x² ≥ 0) - For all real numbers, their square is non-negative
Set Theory:
∀x(x ∈ ℕ → x + 1 ∈ ℕ) - Natural numbers are closed under addition by 1
Real-world:
∀x(x is a mammal → x is warm-blooded)
"All mammals are warm-blooded"
- Mathematical theorems
- Logical necessity
- Set theory axioms
- Database queries
Existential Quantifier
Definition:
Denoted by ∃x P(x), asserts that predicate P holds for at least one element x in the domain of discourse. Read as 'there exists x such that P(x)'
- Distributes over disjunction: ∃x(P(x) ∨ Q(x)) ≡ ∃xP(x) ∨ ∃xQ(x)
- Does not distribute over conjunction: ∃x(P(x) ∧ Q(x)) ≢ ∃xP(x) ∧ ∃xQ(x)
- Can be defined using universal quantifier and negation
- Empty domain: ∃xP(x) is false
- ¬(∃xP(x)) ≡ ∀x¬P(x)
- Double negation: ¬(¬(∃xP(x))) ≡ ∃xP(x)
- Used in constructive proofs
Mathematical:
∃x(x² = 2) - There exists a number whose square is 2
Set Theory:
∃x(x ∈ ℕ ∧ x + 1 = 1) - There exists a natural number that when added to 1 equals 1
Real-world:
∃x(x is a planet ∧ x has rings)
"There exists a planet that has rings"
- ∃!x P(x): exactly one element satisfies P
- ∃x(P(x) ∧ ∀y(P(y) → y = x))
- Important in mathematical definitions
Formal Logic
Satisfiability
Definition:
A logical formula is satisfiable if there exists at least one assignment of truth values to its variables that makes the entire formula true. Formally: ∃x₁...∃xₙ φ(x₁,...,xₙ) = true
- NP-complete problem (SAT)
- Related to validity: φ valid ⇔ ¬φ unsatisfiable
- Independent of syntax
- Preserved under logical equivalence
- Boolean Satisfiability (SAT)
- Horn-SAT (conjunction of Horn clauses)
- 2-SAT (clauses with at most 2 literals)
- 3-SAT (clauses with at most 3 literals)
Satisfiable Formula:
(P ∨ Q) ∧ (¬P ∨ R)
Satisfied by P=true, Q=false, R=true
Unsatisfiable Formula:
P ∧ ¬P
No assignment can make this true
- Automated theorem proving
- Circuit design verification
- Constraint satisfaction
- Planning problems
Logical Form
Definition:
The underlying structure of a logical statement abstracted from its specific content, revealing the logical relationships between its components.
- Atomic propositions
- Logical connectives
- Quantifiers
- Variables and constants
- Predicates and relations
- Reveals logical structure
- Enables formal analysis
- Facilitates proof construction
- Shows logical equivalence
Natural Language:
"All humans are mortal and Socrates is human"
Logical Form:
(∀x(H(x) → M(x))) ∧ H(s)
Natural Language:
"Either it's raining or someone left the sprinkler on"
Logical Form:
R ∨ ∃x(P(x) ∧ S(x))
- Standardization of variables
- Removal of ambiguity
- Explicit quantifier scope
- Prenex normal form
- Skolemization
Logical Consistency
Definition:
A set of statements is logically consistent if and only if there exists at least one interpretation under which all statements in the set are true simultaneously. Formally: ∃M(M ⊨ φ₁ ∧ φ₂ ∧ ... ∧ φₙ)
- Binary property of sets of statements
- Independent of actual truth values
- Preserved under logical equivalence
- Related to satisfiability of conjunction
- Truth table analysis
- Model finding
- Proof by contradiction
- Semantic tableaux
Consistent Set:
1. All birds can fly
2. Penguins are birds
3. Some birds cannot fly
(Consistent because not all birds must fly)
Inconsistent Set:
1. All birds can fly
2. Penguins are birds
3. Penguins cannot fly
4. All penguins must be able to fly
(Contradicts itself about penguins' ability to fly)
- Database integrity
- Knowledge base verification
- Legal reasoning
- Scientific theory development
Formal System
Definition:
A mathematical structure consisting of a formal language L, a set of axioms A, and a set of inference rules R that together define valid derivations. Denoted as FS = (L, A, R)
- Formal language (syntax)
- Formation rules
- Transformation rules
- Axioms or axiom schemas
- Inference rules
- Consistency: no contradictions derivable
- Completeness: all truths derivable
- Soundness: only valid conclusions derivable
- Decidability: existence of decision procedure
Propositional Logic:
- Language: P, Q, R, ∧, ∨, ¬, →, (, )
- Axioms: P∨¬P, (P→Q)→((Q→R)→(P→R))
- Rules: Modus Ponens
Peano Arithmetic:
- Language: 0, S, +, ×, =
- Axioms: ∀x(S(x)≠0), ∀x∀y(S(x)=S(y)→x=y)
- Rules: Mathematical induction
- Mathematical logic
- Programming language semantics
- Automated theorem proving
- Type theory
Formal Language
Definition:
A set of strings over an alphabet Σ, defined by precise formation rules. L ⊆ Σ*
- Alphabet (set of symbols)
- Grammar rules
- Well-formed formulas
- Syntax rules
- Semantics (interpretation)
- Regular languages
- Context-free languages
- Context-sensitive languages
- Recursively enumerable languages
Propositional Logic:
Alphabet: {P, Q, R, ∧, ∨, ¬, →, (, )}
WFF: P∧Q, (P→Q)∨R, ¬(P∧¬Q)
First-Order Logic:
Alphabet: {∀, ∃, P, f, x, y, =, ∧, ∨, ¬}
WFF: ∀x∃yP(x,y), ∀x(P(x)→Q(x))
- Programming languages
- Logic systems
- Compiler design
- Protocol specification
Symbolic Representation
Definition:
A formal system of notation using well-defined symbols to express logical relationships and operations with precision and clarity
- Propositional variables: P, Q, R
- Logical connectives: ∧, ∨, ¬, →, ↔
- Quantifiers: ∀, ∃
- Grouping symbols: (, ), [, ]
- Polish notation (prefix)
- Reverse Polish notation (postfix)
- Infix notation
- Abstract syntax trees
Classical Expression:
((P → Q) ∧ P) → Q
Polish Notation:
→∧→PQP Q
Abstract Syntax Tree:
→
∧ Q
→P P
- Unambiguous interpretation
- Formal manipulation rules
- Computer processability
- Mathematical rigor
Propositional Calculus
Definition:
A formal system dealing with propositions and logical connectives, where formulas are built from atomic propositions using logical operators
- Atomic propositions: P, Q, R...
- Logical connectives: ∧, ∨, ¬, →, ↔
- Well-formed formulas (WFF)
- Inference rules
- Axiom schemas
- Decidable
- Sound and complete
- Compact
- Truth-functional
Basic WFFs:
P ∧ Q
¬(P ∨ Q) → R
(P → Q) ↔ (¬Q → ¬P)
Natural Language:
"If it rains (P) and it's cold (Q), then I'll stay home (R)"
Formalized: (P ∧ Q) → R
- Digital circuit design
- Boolean algebra
- Program verification
- Expert systems
First-order Logic
Definition:
A formal system extending propositional logic with quantifiers (∀, ∃) and predicates, allowing expression of relationships and properties
- Variables: x, y, z...
- Constants: a, b, c...
- Predicates: P(x), Q(x,y)...
- Functions: f(x), g(x,y)...
- Quantifiers: ∀, ∃
- Terms: variables, constants, functions
- Atomic formulas: predicates applied to terms
- Quantified formulas: ∀x P(x), ∃x P(x)
- Complex formulas: combinations with connectives
Mathematical:
"Every natural number has a successor"
∀x∃y(S(y,x))
Real-world:
"Some student knows all topics"
∃x(Student(x) ∧ ∀y(Topic(y) → Knows(x,y)))
- Cannot quantify over predicates
- Cannot express finite cardinality directly
- Some mathematical concepts require schemas
- Not categorical for infinite structures
Higher-order Logic
Definition:
A logical system allowing quantification over predicates, functions, and other higher-order objects, extending first-order logic's expressiveness
- Predicate quantification
- Function quantification
- Type hierarchy
- Lambda abstraction
- Second-order: quantification over sets/predicates
- Third-order: quantification over sets of sets
- ω-order: arbitrary finite orders
- Type theory connection
Second-order:
"Every non-empty property has a minimal element"
∀P((∃xP(x)) → (∃y(P(y) ∧ ∀z(P(z) → y≤z))))
Set theory:
"Two sets are equal if they have the same elements"
∀X∀Y(∀z(z∈X ↔ z∈Y) → X=Y)
- Mathematical foundations
- Type theory
- Program verification
- Category theory
Limitations:
- Incomplete semantics
- Undecidable
- Model-theoretic complexity
Interpretation
Definition:
A mapping I from a formal language L to a domain D that assigns semantic meaning to the symbols and expressions of L. Written as I: L → D
- Domain (universe of discourse)
- Function symbols interpretation
- Predicate symbols interpretation
- Constant symbols interpretation
- Truth value assignment
- Homomorphic structure
- Preserves logical operations
- Unique evaluation of terms
- Satisfaction relation (⊨)
Arithmetic Interpretation:
Domain: Natural numbers
0: zero element
S: successor function
+: addition function
×: multiplication function
Set-theoretic Interpretation:
Domain: Power set of natural numbers
∈: membership relation
∪: union operation
∩: intersection operation
- Model checking
- Semantics definition
- Consistency proofs
- Theory comparison
Model Theory
Definition:
Mathematical study of the relationship between formal theories T and their models M, where M ⊨ T denotes M is a model of T
- Satisfaction (⊨)
- Elementary equivalence
- Theory completeness
- Model completeness
- Compactness Theorem
- Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems
- Completeness Theorem
- Preservation Theorems
Field Theory:
- Real numbers as model
- Complex numbers as model
- Finite fields as models
Group Theory:
- Symmetric groups
- Cyclic groups
- Matrix groups
- Mathematical logic
- Universal algebra
- Algebraic geometry
- Computer science
- Elementary chains
- Ultraproducts
- Back-and-forth construction
- Model companions
Proof Methods
Natural Deduction
Definition:
A proof system that models logical reasoning through introduction and elimination rules for logical connectives. Proofs are trees of judgments Γ ⊢ φ
- Introduction rules (I-rules)
- Elimination rules (E-rules)
- Structural rules
- Derived rules
- ∧-Introduction: P, Q ⊢ P∧Q
- ∨-Elimination: P∨Q, [P⊢R], [Q⊢R] ⊢ R
- →-Introduction: [P⊢Q] ⊢ P→Q
- ∀-Introduction: [a]⊢P(a) ⊢ ∀xP(x)
Proof of P∧Q ⊢ Q∧P:
1. P∧Q (premise)
2. P (∧-elimination)
3. Q (∧-elimination)
4. Q∧P (∧-introduction)
Proof of P, P→Q ⊢ Q:
1. P (premise)
2. P→Q (premise)
3. Q (→-elimination)
- Local rules
- Assumption management
- Normal forms
- Cut elimination
Sequent Calculus
Definition:
A formal proof system using sequents of the form Γ ⊢ Δ, where Γ and Δ are finite multisets of formulas. Read as 'Γ entails Δ'
- Left rules (operating on Γ)
- Right rules (operating on Δ)
- Structural rules (weakening, contraction)
- Cut rule (transitivity of entailment)
- Cut elimination theorem
- Subformula property
- Decidability for propositional logic
- Conservative extension
Basic Rules:
Axiom: A ⊢ A
Cut: (Γ ⊢ Δ,A) and (A,Π ⊢ Λ) implies (Γ,Π ⊢ Δ,Λ)
Sample Derivation:
1. P ⊢ P (axiom)
2. P,Q ⊢ P (weakening)
3. P,Q ⊢ P∨Q (∨-right)
- Proof theory
- Automated theorem proving
- Type systems
- Program verification
Proof Theory
Definition:
Study of formal proofs as mathematical objects and the structural relationships between them
- Formal proof systems
- Proof normalization
- Cut elimination
- Proof search
- Natural deduction
- Sequent calculus
- Hilbert systems
- Resolution calculus
- Normalization theorem
- Cut-elimination theorem
- Herbrand's theorem
- Consistency proofs
- Automated theorem proving
- Program verification
- Type theory
- Constructive mathematics
- Structural induction
- Proof transformation
- Term rewriting
- Proof mining
Natural Deduction:
Proof of A∧B ⊢ B∧A
1. A∧B premise
2. A ∧-elimination
3. B ∧-elimination
4. B∧A ∧-introduction
Sequent Calculus:
Proof of ⊢ A→(B→(A∧B))
1. A,B ⊢ A axiom
2. A,B ⊢ B axiom
3. A,B ⊢ A∧B ∧-right
4. A ⊢ B→(A∧B) →-right
5. ⊢ A→(B→(A∧B)) →-right
Construction Sequence
Definition:
An ordered sequence of steps S = (s₁, s₂, ..., sₙ) that, when executed in order, produces a valid logical structure or proof
- Initial state
- Transformation rules
- Intermediate states
- Final state
- Well-defined steps
- Preserves validity
- Deterministic
- Finite length
Formula Construction:
1. Start with P
2. Add conjunction: P ∧
3. Add second operand: P ∧ Q
4. Add parentheses: (P ∧ Q)
Proof Construction:
1. State premises
2. Apply inference rule
3. State intermediate conclusion
4. Repeat until goal reached
- Proof building
- Expression parsing
- Tree construction
- Formula generation
Structural Induction
Definition:
A proof technique establishing that a property P holds for all instances of a recursively defined structure S by showing it holds for base cases and is preserved by construction steps
- Base case(s)
- Inductive hypothesis
- Construction rules
- Inductive step
- Prove for atomic elements
- Assume for substructures
- Prove for composite
- Consider all constructions
List Induction:
Base: P(empty list)
Step: P(list) → P(cons(x,list))
Tree Induction:
Base: P(leaf)
Step: P(left) ∧ P(right) → P(node(left,right))
Formula Induction:
Base: P(atomic formulas)
Step: P(φ) ∧ P(ψ) → P(φ∘ψ)
- Data structure properties
- Program correctness
- Grammar validation
- Type systems
Logical Principles
Non-contradiction
Definition:
The logical principle that asserts ¬(P ∧ ¬P) is always true. No statement can be both true and false in the same sense at the same time
- Foundational to classical logic
- Related to consistency
- Independent of excluded middle
- Preserved under substitution
- Propositional: ¬(P ∧ ¬P)
- Predicate: ¬∃x(P(x) ∧ ¬P(x))
- Modal: □¬(P ∧ ¬P)
- Semantic: not(P is true and P is false)
Classical:
"A circle cannot be both round and not round"
Mathematical:
"A number cannot be both prime and composite"
Logical:
"A proposition cannot be both true and false"
- Aristotelian foundation
- Intuitionistic acceptance
- Dialectical challenges
- Quantum interpretations
Law Of Excluded Middle
Definition:
The principle that every proposition P is either true or false, formally expressed as P ∨ ¬P
- Tautology in classical logic
- Not accepted in intuitionistic logic
- Independent of non-contradiction
- Basis for proof by contradiction
- Propositional: P ∨ ¬P
- Predicate: ∀x(P(x) ∨ ¬P(x))
- Modal: □(P ∨ ¬P)
- Semantic: P is true or P is false
Classical:
"Either it is raining or it is not raining"
Mathematical:
"A number is either prime or not prime"
Set Theory:
"An element is either in a set or not in a set"
- Proof by contradiction
- Classical mathematics
- Boolean algebra
- Digital logic
Necessary And Sufficient Conditions
Definition:
P is necessary for Q if Q → P, and P is sufficient for Q if P → Q. If both hold, then P ↔ Q
- Necessary: Q cannot be true without P being true
- Sufficient: P being true guarantees Q is true
- Necessary and Sufficient: P ↔ Q (biconditional)
- Neither: P and Q are logically independent
- Necessary: Q → P
- Sufficient: P → Q
- Both: P ↔ Q
- Neither: No logical connection
Mathematical:
Being a square is sufficient (but not necessary) for being a rectangle
Having four equal sides is necessary (but not sufficient) for being a square
Being divisible by both 2 and 3 is necessary and sufficient for being divisible by 6
Real-world:
Being 18 is necessary (but not sufficient) for voting
Having a valid passport is sufficient (but not necessary) for ID
Being a US citizen and 35+ years old is necessary and sufficient for presidential eligibility
- Mathematical proofs
- Legal reasoning
- Scientific explanation
- Policy analysis
Formal Language
String
Definition:
A finite sequence s = a₁a₂...aₙ where each aᵢ belongs to an alphabet Σ. Formally written as s ∈ Σ*
- Has finite length |s|
- Can be empty (ε)
- Can be concatenated
- Has substrings
- Concatenation (s₁·s₂)
- Reversal (sᴿ)
- Substring extraction
- Length computation
Over alphabet Σ = {a,b}:
Empty string: ε
Simple strings: a, ab, baa
Concatenation: ab·ba = abba
In formal logic:
Well-formed formula: (P∧Q)→R
Not well-formed: )P∧(
- Formal languages
- Pattern matching
- Computability theory
- Programming languages
Expression
Definition:
A syntactically valid combination of symbols according to formation rules of a formal system
- Atomic expressions
- Compound expressions
- Well-formed formulas
- Terms and formulas
- Constants
- Variables
- Operators
- Delimiters
- Functions
Logical Expressions:
P ∧ (Q ∨ R)
∀x(P(x) → Q(x))
Mathematical Expressions:
2x + 3y = 5
∫₀¹ x² dx
- Precedence rules
- Scope rules
- Type rules
- Syntactic categories
- Well-formedness
- Unambiguous parsing
- Type correctness
- Semantic meaning
Structures
Syntax Tree
Definition:
A hierarchical data structure T = (V,E,r) representing the grammatical structure of an expression, where V is the set of nodes, E the edges, and r the root
- Hierarchical structure
- Unique root node
- Directed edges
- Preserves operator precedence
- Abstract syntax trees (AST)
- Parse trees
- Derivation trees
- Expression trees
- Compiler design
- Expression evaluation
- Language processing
- Proof representation
Node
Definition:
A fundamental unit v ∈ V in a tree structure containing data and maintaining relationships with other nodes through edges E
- Contains data/value
- Has parent (except root)
- May have children
- Has depth/level
- Root node
- Internal nodes
- Leaf nodes
- Operator nodes
- Parent-child
- Siblings
- Ancestors
- Descendants
Logical Operators:
Node(∧): connects conjuncts
Node(∨): connects disjuncts
Node(¬): unary negation
Expression Trees:
Node(+): addition operator
Node(2): numeric literal
Node(x): variable
- Node creation
- Child addition/removal
- Value modification
- Tree traversal
Leaf Node
Definition:
A terminal node l ∈ V in a tree structure with no children, formally: l ∈ V such that ∄v ∈ V: (l,v) ∈ E
- No children
- Terminal element
- Contains atomic data
- Always has parent (except if root)
- Degree = 0
- Terminal in traversal
- Contains primitive values
- Cannot be expanded
In Expression Trees:
- Variables (x, y, z)
- Constants (2, 3.14, true)
- Atomic propositions (P, Q, R)
In Parse Trees:
- Tokens
- Literals
- Identifiers
- Terminal symbols
- Expression evaluation
- Tree traversal endpoints
- Pattern matching
- Value storage
Root Node
Definition:
The unique node r ∈ V in a tree structure with no parent, serving as the origin point. Formally: r ∈ V such that ∄v ∈ V: (v,r) ∈ E
- No parent node
- Unique in tree
- Level/depth 0
- Ancestor of all nodes
- Entry point for traversal
- Contains main operator/function
- Defines scope/context
- Maximum in partial ordering
Expression Trees:
P ∧ (Q ∨ R):
Root = ∧ (main connective)
Function Application:
f(g(x)):
Root = f (outermost function)
Arithmetic:
(2 + 3) × 4:
Root = × (last operation)
- Tree initialization
- Subtree access
- Structure modification
- Tree rebalancing
Branch
Definition:
A directed edge e = (u,v) ∈ E in a tree structure connecting a parent node u to a child node v
- Directed relationship
- Unique parent end
- Weight/cost possible
- Represents hierarchy
- Left branch
- Right branch
- Ordered branches
- Weighted branches
Binary Operations:
∧-branches: connect to both operands
¬-branch: connects to single operand
Function Application:
f(x,y): two branches to arguments
Parse Trees:
IF-THEN: branches to condition and body
- Branch creation
- Branch deletion
- Path traversal
- Tree restructuring
Degree Of Syntax Tree
Definition:
The maximum number d of child nodes for any node v in the tree T. Formally: d = max{|children(v)| : v ∈ V}
- Fixed for specific types
- Affects tree balance
- Influences traversal
- Impacts complexity
- Binary trees (d=2)
- Ternary trees (d=3)
- N-ary trees
- Variable degree trees
Logical Operators:
¬ (degree 1)
∧,∨,→,↔ (degree 2)
IF-THEN-ELSE (degree 3)
Function Application:
f(x) (degree 1)
g(x,y) (degree 2)
h(x,y,z) (degree 3)
- Storage requirements
- Processing efficiency
- Tree balancing
- Algorithm design