Visual Tools
Calculators
Tables
Mathematical Keyboard
Converters
Other Tools

Tautology




Definition and Notation

A tautology is a proposition that is always true, regardless of the truth values of its components. In propositional logic, a tautology is a formula that evaluates to true under all possible truth assignments.
Example:
P¬PP∨¬P
(The law of the excluded middle: "P or not P" is always true.)
The notation commonly used for tautology in logic is:

\top

(The top symbol, also called "verum" or "true constant").

Alternatively, a tautology can be denoted explicitly as:

P\vdash P

which means "P is provable" or "P is always true".

In some texts, tautologies are also expressed using equivalence sign like this:

PP \equiv \top

to explicitly state that a proposition (P)( P ) is always true (equivalent to true).

Tautology vs Equivalence

Are all equivalences tautologies?

As the definition of equivalence states, two propositions 𝐴𝐴 and 𝐵𝐵 are logically equivalent if they always have the same truth value in every possible scenario. This means that their truth tables are identical. This is a bilateral relationship meaning both expressions evaluate to true together or false together in all cases. It does not matter if they are true or false, the key here is that they are the same (equal).
Example:

(𝑃𝑄)(¬𝑃𝑄)(𝑃→𝑄)≡(¬𝑃∨𝑄)

(Material implication rewritten in disjunctive form.)
As long as the equivalence is valid -the overall bilateral expression as a whole evaluates to true and falls under definition of tautology.
So the final answer to that question is YES , as long as equivalence is valid- it is a tautology.

Are all tautologies logical equivalences?

According to definition, a tautology is about a single proposition that is always true, while equivalence is a relationship between two propositions that always have the same truth value.
A tautology must always evaluate to true, but it does not necessarily have to express a relationship between two statements.In fact, there are numerous tautologies that are unilateral expressions that evaluate to true in all possible valuations but don't express a relationship of equality between two propositions.
Examples:
Law of Excluded Middle:
P¬PP∨¬P
Always true, but doesn't equate two propositions.

Self-implication:
PPP→P
Tautological but doesn't equate different propositions.
More examples:

P(PQ)P ∨ (P → Q)

(PQ)(QP)(P → Q) ∨ (Q → P)

P(Q(PQ))P → (Q → (P ∧ Q))

All those are tautologies that do not fall under the definition of equivalence.

This distinction means that while every valid equivalence is a tautology, not each tautology is equivalence because some tautologies do not express a two-sided relationship between two propositions.
This means that the set of all logical equivalences is a subset of the set of all tautologies.




Tautologies (e.g., P → P, P ∨ ¬P) Equivalences (e.g., P ↔ Q, when logically equivalent) P ↔ Q where P and Q are equivalent but not named laws Non-equivalence tautologies (e.g., ((P → Q) → P) → P, (¬P → P) → P)


Logic Laws as Tautologies

As discussed in previous section, valid equivalence is bilateral statement evaluating to true and in this way it is a tautology.
Since all propositional logic laws are either equivalences or directly tautological statements, we conclude that all propositional logic laws are tautologies.

Propositional Logic Laws as Equivalences

Many fundamental laws of propositional logic are expressed as equivalences, meaning both sides of the equation always yield the same truth value. Since the equivalence itself must always hold, it is a tautology.
Examples:
De Morgan’s Laws:

¬(𝑃𝑄)(¬𝑃¬𝑄)¬(𝑃∨𝑄)≡(¬𝑃∧¬𝑄)

¬(PQ)(¬P¬Q)¬(P∧Q)≡(¬P∨¬Q)

Commutative Laws:

PQQPP∨Q≡Q∨P

PQQPP∧Q≡Q∧P

These laws are always true, making them tautologies.See more examples of basic propositional logic laws here.

Propositional Logic Laws That Are Directly Tautologies

Some laws are one-sided expressions that are true in all cases without establishing an equivalence. These are still tautologies.

Law of the Excluded Middle:

P¬PTP∨¬P≡T
This states that every proposition is either true or false, making it a tautology.

Law of Non-Contradiction:

¬(P¬P)T¬(P∧¬P)≡T
This states that no proposition can be both true and false simultaneously, which is always true.

Since all propositional logic laws either express equivalences that are tautologies or standalone tautologies, we conclude that all propositional logic laws are tautologies.

Visit corresponding page to learn more about propositional logic laws.

Use this tool to evaluate truth tables.


Tautologies that are not laws

While all propositional logic laws are tautologies, not all tautologies qualify as laws. A law in logic is a fundamental principle that defines how logical operations behave, often used in formal proofs and reasoning systems.
However, some tautologies are simply valid logical statements that always evaluate to true without establishing a fundamental logical principle.
These non-law tautologies may still be useful in proofs, derivations, or formal logic, but they do not define core logical rules like De Morgan’s Laws or the Law of the Excluded Middle. Instead, they are often the result of specific logical constructions, implications, or transformations that hold universally without being considered foundational.

nameexpressionexplanation
Self-Implication
P → P
If P then P - a proposition always implies itself
Non-Contradiction
¬(P ∧ ¬P)
Not both P and not P - contradictions cannot be true
Self-Equivalence
P ↔ P
P if and only if P - a proposition is always equivalent to itself
Modus Ponens Form
((P → Q) ∧ P) → Q
If P implies Q and P is true, then Q must be true
Hypothetical Syllogism
((P → Q) ∧ (Q → R)) → (P → R)
If P implies Q and Q implies R, then P implies R
Weakening
P → (Q → P)
If P is true, then it remains true regardless of Q
Proof by Contradiction Form
(¬P → P) → P
If assuming not-P leads to P, then P must be true
Peirce's Law
((P → Q) → P) → P
Classical logical principle not provable in intuitionistic logic
Disjunctive Weakening
P ∨ (P → Q)
Either P is true or if P then Q - always true
Implication Disjunction
(P → Q) ∨ (Q → P)
Either P implies Q or Q implies P - always true
Conjunction Implication
(P → Q) → ((P ∧ R) → Q)
If P implies Q, then P and R together also imply Q
Conjunction Introduction Form
P → (Q → (P ∧ Q))
If P and Q are both true, their conjunction is true
Modus Ponens Alternative Form
(P ∧ (P → Q)) → Q
If P is true and P implies Q, then Q is true
Modus Tollens Form
(¬Q ∧ (P → Q)) → ¬P
If Q is false and P implies Q, then P must be false
Self-Contradiction Implication
(P → ¬P) → ¬P
If P implies its own negation, then P must be false
Implication Negation Equivalence
¬(P → Q) ↔ (P ∧ ¬Q)
An implication is false only when its antecedent is true and consequent is false
Contradiction Implication
(P → (Q ∧ ¬Q)) → ¬P
If P implies a contradiction, then P must be false
Double Negation Implication
((P → Q) ∧ (P → ¬Q)) → ¬P
If P implies both Q and not-Q, then P must be false
Triple Negation Implication
(P → Q) → ((P → ¬Q) → ¬P)
If P implies contradictory results, P must be false
Material Implication Alternative
(P → Q) → (¬P ∨ Q)
If P implies Q, then either P is false or Q is true
Disjunctive Implication
(P ∨ Q) → (¬P → Q)
If either P or Q is true, then not-P implies Q
Hypothetical Syllogism Disjunctive Form
((P → Q) ∧ (R → S) ∧ (P ∨ R)) → (Q ∨ S)
Complex syllogism with disjunctive conclusion
Biconditional Expansion
(P ↔ Q) ↔ ((P → Q) ∧ (Q → P))
P if and only if Q means P implies Q and Q implies P

Use this tool to generate truth tables dynamically and evaluate those expressions.